In
the Summa Theologica (I, Q
85, A 6), St. Thomas argues that the intellect cannot err with
respect to a thing's essence. This seems counter-intuitive, as
Thomas himself wrote an entire work on properly understanding
essence. So why one cannot err in apprehending essence is not
entirely clear. In order to understand what is meant by his claim,
we will determine what the intellect is, how it operates, what an
essence is, and what is meant by error on the part of the intellect.
To the question treated in the Summa,
we being with the sed contra:
Augustine says
(Questions. 83, qu. 32), that "everyone who is deceived, does
not rightly understand that wherein he is deceived." And the
Philosopher says (De Anima iii, 10), that "the intellect is
always true."1
This gives us a
two-pronged approach to the problem. On one hand, there is the
proposition that deception implies an imperfect operation of
the intellect. On the other hand, there is the proposition that the
intellect itself is true by nature. This prompts an account
of exactly what the intellect is, for if there is error or deception
at all, it would seem to be on account of the intellect (as is stated
in objections 1 and 2 of the same question).2
The intellect is
understood as being passive in that it is predisposed to what is
intelligible, as Thomas explains, “[T]he human intellect, which is
the lowest in the order of intelligence and most remote from the
perfection of the Divine intellect, is in potentiality with regard to
things intelligible, and is at first 'like a clean tablet on which
nothing is written,' as the Philosopher says.”3
Aristotle likewise compares the intellect to the senses because of
its passivity to external objects. But neither intellect nor sense
is purely passive. Though the senses receive impressions from
external objects, they are passive only in that they are potentially
receptive to their proper objects.4
In a similar way, the passive
intellect receives external objects, and is potential
to them in the sense that it must lack the natures which it
apprehends, as Thomas explains, “if the intellect were restricted
to any particular nature, this connatural restriction would prevent
it from knowing other natures.”5
We can see this analogously in the eye: It is incorrect to say that
the eye contains light and color by its nature, rather that it is by
nature receptive to light and color. Moreover, the intelligible
forms which we perceive in matter exist in matter, though
matter is not intelligible per se.
What makes them intelligible is the power of the active
intellect which discerns form from matter by
abstraction.6
So the intellect, in order to know, must have a nature that is
distinct from all the other things that it knows. Therefore, if it
can know all sensible things, it must be distinct from any sensible
nature. This precludes any notion of the intellect as a bodily
organ, which leads us to conclude that the intellect must be
something immaterial.7
That the intellect
is immaterial helps us to understand how it is passive in one respect
but active in another. While both intellect and the bodily senses
are receptive to their proper objects (not in the same way but
analogously), they are each active in different ways. As Thomas
explains, “the difference is that sensitivity acts in the body, but
the intellect acts on its own.”8
We can see this in the effects their proper objects have on their
operation: The eye sees by receiving light, so that the material
organ is effected by a material object. Too much of its object can
overwhelm the organ, as when the eye is blinded by an excess of
light. But the intellect is never overwhelmed by “too much truth.”
Rather than being blinded or brought low by its object, the
intellect is strengthened in its operation such that what was
difficult to receive at first makes it see all other objects more
easily.9
Because the intellect acquires knowledge primarily through the
senses, its activity presupposes the activity of the senses. But
because the intellect does not of necessity work through some bodily
organ, it works by its own intrinsic principle.
As said above, the
intellect is receptive to truth as a kind of potency. It acquires
knowledge with reference to sensible things, but it works in itself
from the self-evident first principles that it possesses by nature.
And there are also principles external to a man which can aid in the
acquisition of knowledge. So there are two principles involved in
the activity of acquiring knowledge, extrinsic and intrinsic;
extrinsic in what man learns by instruction and intrinsic in what he
discovers by his own act. Because the intellect acts by an
intrinsic principle, it acts on an active potency.10
Hence instruction, being an extrinsic principle, is something
secondary to the activity of the intellect, and is not necessary for
its perfect operation. In order to ascertain whether it is possible
for the intellect to err with respect to its own operation, we should
focus primarily on the intrinsic principle of knowledge.
Having given an
account of the intellect, what it is and by what principle it
operates, we have now to explore how the intellect understands its
object. We have already mentioned that matter is not in itself
intelligible but that the intellect nevertheless understands in
connection with the sensitive faculties. While matter itself is not
something which the intellect directly apprehends it is perceived
through the senses. And it is from its perception through the senses
that the intellect creates an image (a
phantasm) of what is perceived from which it can abstract the
intelligible form.11
According to St. Thomas, one can abstract in two ways. One way is
to consider something to be separate from that in which it is
understood as if they were separate in reality; e.g. if one were to
abstract “red” from “surface,” taking the color to be
something distinct and separate from colored surfaces. This type of
abstraction admits error, because the intellect in this way does not
consider things as they are. The second way in which the intellect
can abstract is to consider something absolutely, such that we
disregard those things which are not necessary to the thing in
question; e.g. if we consider “red” apart from “apple,” we
are not erroneously understanding what “red” is but regarding
“apple” as something unnecessary to redness. Simply put, we may
correctly understand “red” by itself as an (accidental) essence,
but we cannot understand it as something which exists by itself.12
Aristotle's insight
into the process of understanding is crucial to forming a complete
account of the intellect's operation. In the beginning of the
Physics he explains,
[T]he
natural road is from what is more familiar and clearer to us to what
is clearer and better known by nature; for it is not the same things
that are well known to us and well known simply. For this reason it
is necessary to lead ourselves forward in this way; from what is less
clear by nature but clearer to us
to what is clearer and better known by nature. But the things that
are first evident and clear to us are more so the ones that are
jumbled together, but later the elements and beginnings become known
to those who separate them out from these. Thus it is necessary to
proceed from what is general to what is particular, for it is the
whole that is better known by perceiving, and what is general is a
kind of whole since it embraces many things as though they were
parts.13
So,
taking as the object of intellection what is perceived by the senses,
the intellect begins its process of coming to know with a general and
confused image of things, and from there proceeds by means of
abstraction to a more precise knowledge of things in themselves.
Thomas expounds on this when he says, “the perfect act of the
intellect is complete knowledge, when the object is distinctly and
determinately known; whereas the incomplete act is imperfect
knowledge, when the object is known indistinctly, and as it were
confusedly.”14
So we refer to the act of the intellect from its active potency as
being perfected in the complete and determinate knowledge of its
object. But this process is not possible without having a starting
point which is found in the first principles.15
Yet how these first principles are acquired must be explained in
order to complete our account of the process of coming to know.
According
to Aristotle, the first principles required for knowledge are neither
innate, for infants would be as capable of knowledge as a grown man,
nor are they acquired at some later point, for learning and discovery
would be impossible until then. Because knowledge is acquired
through sense-perception, he concludes that the first principles are
gathered from sense-perception and the accumulation of memory which,
over time, make up experience.
Irrational animals have the capacity of both sense-perception and
memory, but they are not capable of gathering the principles of
knowledge which is a capacity of the intellectual soul.16
Thomas elaborates on this by reference to the agent intellect,
reminding us that the intellect is not merely passive but must
actively derive the universal from the experience of particulars.17
We
are now equipped to give a complete account of the intellectual
operation in man. A man begins by perceiving sensible objects
through his senses (rust, a hard surface, heaviness, etc.). The
objects of his senses are unintelligible, but his passive intellect
receives an image of the thing perceived and holds this in memory.
After many instances of this, the agent intellect is able to abstract
from his experience a universal principle (the concept of iron).
With the universal now in mind, he is able to proceed to knowledge of
particulars (knowing what iron is in general, he can identify
particular bodies of iron). It is clear from this that the intellect
understands its object by combination and division.18
This is easily seen with respect to the twofold composition of
material things. In one sense a thing is composed of form and
matter, in another sense it is composed of substance and accidents.
The intellect divides with respect to both these compositions, as our
very consideration of them attests, and in combination we acknowledge
those composites to be whole in reality.19
With
the intellect and its operations accounted for, we now consider what
essence is. Aristotle explains, “a thing's essence is what a thing
is.”20
An essence is like a definition, and is indeed expressed by a
definition, but is strictly speaking a definition of a thing in its
own right, rather than a property or something which can only exist
parasitically on something else: E.g. 'man' or 'tree' is an essence
but 'white' is not, because 'white' only exists as a property which
adheres to man or tree. There are however essential properties of
man which are not accidental. “Bipedal”, for instance, is an
essential part of 'man'. There is a correspondence here to species,
as 'man' is a species of the genus 'animal', and one of the
differentiae which distinguishes 'man' from 'cow' is “bipedal,”
though “bipedal” itself is not an essence. Aristotle thus
concludes, “essence will not be found in any of those things which
are not a species of a genus.”21
To
understand an essence is the same as to identify it. That
is, the question, “why is that a man” can be answered by
explaining what a man is, and vice versa.22
So, in a general sense, an essence is what a thing is. Depending on
what is meant by a “thing” however, there can be a distinction
between an essence and a thing. For example, a man is a composite of
form and matter. Thus the question “what is a man?” cannot be
answered without reference to a body and its constituents. To the
question “why is that body a man's body?” the answer will refer
to the form which makes the body a man's body. The distinction
between the composite and the components points to the substantial
form which composes the elements into a whole: E.g. Even though a
man by definition has body parts, a collection of body parts is not a
man.23
Essence, in the formulation of its definition, is generally
understood with regard to species (though the two terms are not
strictly synonymous). A species is a member of some genus which is
distinguished from other species of that genus by some difference.;
for instance, 'man' is defined as a 'rational animal'. He is
generically an animal and specifically rational, 'rational' being the
key difference from other animals. It is important to note that man
is distinct from animals in species, but not in genus. Man is an
animal, albeit a rational one.24
Though there are many men in the species 'man', the species itself
is one, as Thomas says,
“[I]t is evident that a multiplicity of parts in a definition does
not signify a multiplicity of essential parts of which the essence is
constituted as if they were distinct things; but all signify one
thing which is made determinate by an ultimate difference. It is also
evident from this that there is one substantial form for every
species.”25
An essence is
expressed by a definition, so that there are many men does not prove
that there are many essences or species of man, because where and how
many they are does not belong to the definition of man. Neither does
the multiplicity of “parts” implicit in the definition (for
example man's two legs) mean that there are many essences within an
essence, because essence belongs primarily to substance, but each of
those so-called parts do not exist as a substance.26
So one could say that there is a definition of “leg” and thus
that a leg has in a certain sense an essence, but a leg is not a
substance. Furthermore, a leg is defined as
part of a body, so it cannot be a leg unless it is subsumed under the
essence of the thing to which it belongs.
What we have considered thus far is essence in terms of its
definition. But we should consider essence in terms of being as
well. As regards to what a thing is
in itself, essence is the composite of form and matter.27
It is by its essence that an individual thing participates in being.
This is not to say that everything which has an essence also has
being, but that all things which exist do so insofar as they have an
essence. As noted above, it belongs to the species of material
beings to have matter, but not this or that matter. The prerequisite
matter for a given species is called indeterminate matter,
while the matter by which an individual participates in the species
is called determinate.
Therefore material things in particular participate in a species
through determinate matter and, by the same token, are distinct from
other individuals who share the same essence.28
Though essence is the composition of form and matter, neither the
form nor the matter are separate in reality, this means that essence
cannot be broken into parts: It is understood by combining terms
(form and matter, genus and difference, etc.) into a definition, but
an essence is a distinct unity in reality.
Now
that it is clear what the intellect is and how it operates, as well
as what essence is and how it is known, we may at last consider
Thomas' argument in full. He recalls the comparison between sense
and intellect, viz. that both are always directed to their proper
object, adding that, “as long as the faculty exists, its judgment
concerning its own proper object does not fail.”29
The senses may be deceived with respect objects that are “common,”
such as size or color; e.g. the eye perceives the sun to be yellow
and an inch across. The senses may also be deceived with respect to
objects in an accidental way; e.g. salt may be mistaken for sugar.
With common objects, the eye is deceived because what is perceives is
other than what it is, as the sun is not yellow nor an inch across.
With the latter case (salt and sugar), the eye is not deceived with
respect to what it apprehends, for it takes the salt to be white and
translucent, but is deceived in conflating its object with what
appears to be an identical object but is in fact different. In both
of these cases, one's sight functions perfectly; it apprehends
precisely what it receives. This is why Thomas says, “as long as
the faculty exists, its judgment concerning its own proper object
does not fail.”30
The
proper object of the intellect is essence (in this instance referred
to as quiddity which simply
emphasizes the “what” of the thing). As we have said, a
thing's essence is what a thing is, and it is something unified which
we come to understand as a composition. So, in an absolute sense, we
have an essence that is indivisible in reality which is apprehended
by the intellect which is immaterial. But in order for the intellect
to understand an essence, it must move to its act of knowing by means
of combination and division. Thus we have two types of error to
consider, the apprehension of an object by the intellect taken
absolutely, and the understanding of it in terms of its definition
(its intellectual composition). If the intellect is said to err with
regard to apprehending something absolutely, as for instance one
might be said to err in his understanding of what “space” is,
then he does not know what it is. There is nothing complex about
this type of “error.” Either one knows it or he does not. In
fact, if one does not know “space” then he is not mistaken about
it, because there is nothing in his mind to mistake. In this regard,
i.e. with things that are apprehended simply, the mind cannot err.
It is only in the process of discerning composition, as it pertains
to a thing's definition, that the mind can be mistaken; for instance,
if one were to regard a circle as a “three-sided figure.”
Another way in which the intellect could err is to combine
incompatible terms into a definition, as for instance in “rational
plant.” The error in both of these examples is attributed either
to the mis-attribution of a definition or to the combination of
incompatible terms into an attempted definition.31
But both of these errors are accidental to intellectual operation.
The result of both of these errors is to fail to understand an
essence completely.
An
analogous way of understanding the truth of intellection is by
considering the various levels of “error” with regard to
apprehension. For example, a young reader may come across a word
never before seen and pronounce it “hoar-is-on.” The mistake is
in combining the syllables in a way that misses the meaning of the
word. The is no “half-understanding” in this regard; the word is
a complete mystery. With help from his teacher, the child learns
that the word is “horizon” and suddenly understands completely.
In another example, a hunter might mistake an elk for a deer. He
does not misapprehend the essence of elk, rather he completely
understands the essence of deer and misappropriates it to the wrong
sense object. Finally, in a more complex case, one might attempt to
define an animal without reference to form or the soul, regarding it
as merely mechanical or “purely material.” In this case, it
should be said that either he does not understand what an animal is
because, while he may understand the parts of its definition, i.e.
the terms “matter,” “body,” “life,” “motion,” etc.
are correctly apprehended, but they are out placed out of order in
that definition. So he does not “half-understand” what an animal
is; he does not understand what an animal is at all, though he
understands all of the parts necessary to combine a correct
definition and come to knowledge of its essence.
It
may seem trivial to argue for the truth of the intellect if what is
meant is simply that error is only in the process of learning and
that substantial ignorance is absolute. But all science (especially
philosophy) is at stake if this distinction is not understood
properly. The intellect has the power to know the truth, it has the
means to attain it, and it knows truth with certainty. That the
means of attaining knowledge is prone to fault does not mean that the
intellect does not know truth, for to say that the intellect is not
true is to say that there is no intellect.
1 ST
I, Q 85, A 6 sed contra.(Benziger
Bros., 1947)
2 Op.
cit. obj 1 & 2
3 ST
I, Q 79, A 2 resp.
4 Aquinas,
Commentary on De Anima,
trans. Foster and Humphries (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1951)
676.
5 Op.
cit. 680.
6 ST
I, Q 79, A 3 resp.
7 Aquinas,
Commentary on De Anima,
681.
8 Op.
cit. 688.
9 Ibid.
10 St.
Thomas Aquinas, On the Teacher in Thomas Aquinas: Selected
Writings, trans. Ralph McInerny (New York, NY: Penguin Books,
1998), 199.
11 ST
I, Q 86, A 1 sed
contra
12 ST
I, Q 86, A 1 resp.
13 Aristotle,
Physics in Aristotle’s Physics: A Guided Study,
trans. Joe Sachs (New Brunswick: Rutgers University Press, 2011), 33
(1.i).
14 ST
I, Q 85, A 3 resp.
15 Physics
99b20
16 Physics
100a4
17 St.
Thomas Aquinas, Commentary on the Posterior Analytics, trans.
Fabian R. Larcher, (http://dhspriory.org/thomas/PostAnalytica.htm),
II, xx.
18 ST
I, Q 85, A 5 resp.
19 ST
I, Q 85, A 5, ad 3
20 St.
Thomas Aquinas, Commentary on the Metaphysics, trans. John P.
Rowan, (Chicago, 1961)
(http://dhspriory.org/thomas/Metaphysics7.htm), VII, iii, 581.
21 Ibid.
22 Aristotle,
Metaphysics in Commentary on the Metaphysics by Thomas
Aquinas, trans. John P. Rowan (Chicago, 1961)
(http://dhspriory.org/thomas/Metaphysics7.htm), 1651.
23
Commentary on Metaphysics, 1674.
24 Aquinas,
Commentary on Metaphysics, 1328.
25 Aquinas,
Commentary on Metaphysics, 1339.
26 Op.
cit., 1339.
27 Thomas
Aquinas, De Ente et Essentia,
trans. Armand Maurer (Toronto: Pontifical Institute of Mediaeval
Studies, 1968), 36 (IV.iii).
28 De
Ente, IV.v
29 ST
I, Q 85, A 6 resp.
30 ibid.
31 ST
I, Q 85, A 6
No comments:
Post a Comment