Wednesday, April 26, 2017

"Christian Libertarian"



Then the [Christian Libertarians] going, consulted among themselves how to ensnare him in his speech.
And they sent to him their disciples with the [Internal Revenue Service], saying: Master, we know that thou art a true speaker, and teachest the way of God in truth, neither carest thou for any man: for thou dost not regard the person of men.
Tell us therefore what dost thou think, is [tax theft], or not?
But Jesus knowing their wickedness, said: Why do you tempt me, ye hypocrites?
Show me [a dollar]. And they offered him [a dollar].
And Jesus saith to them: Whose image and inscription is this?
They say to him: [Washington's]. Then he saith to them: Render to [Washington] the things that are [Washington's]; and to God, the things that are God's.
And hearing this they wondered, and leaving him, went their ways.


Thursday, January 19, 2017

Moral Necessity

     When one takes what is generally considered to be a "moral obligation," such as the golden rule or the Decalogue, and compares such an imperative to its practical application, he will soon find out that, in order to call it a law, he must admit that it is more like a civil law than a scientific law; i.e., the "obligation" is suggested but is not evident.  The word implies being drawn from some binding principle (cf. Latin, ligare), but there is nothing directly binding about these moral imperatives.  God Himself says, "Thou shalt not steal," but people steal all the time, and without divine intervention.  The "obligation" of such imperatives are more commonly understood in the sense that there are consequences for those who would disobey them.  In this sense, the imperative is conditional, and is properly understood as implying an "if" clause: "Thou shalt not steal - if thou wilt be spared," "Do unto others as ye would have them do unto you - if ye wish to inherit the Kingdom," etc.  This is probably the same way most people understand the moral import of civil law, e.g. "pay your taxes - if you wish to avoid punishment," which suggests that the "binding" quality of an obligation is found merely in the connection between an action and its imposed consequences.

     There are still real obligations, however, which are so immediately binding as to be called "moral necessities."  The Golden Rule nor any of the Ten Commandments are moral necessities, properly speaking.  This is simply because of what necessity is:  A necessity is that which cannot be impossible or, in other words, a necessity is something which has no alternative.  Take the 7th Commandment again: "Thou shalt not steal."  If it were a necessity, then nobody would be able to steal and, in which case, it would be superfluous to demand that men keep to their own property.  It could be argued that the very fact of the Commandments being commanded proves that they are not moral necessities, but rather practical rules which are based on necessities.  It may be that moral necessities are so little known precisely because they are necessary and not given to alteration or change of form based on their practical import.

     So, we are led to ask the question, "what then, are the moral necessities?"  Moral necessities can be found in what is called the "Natural Law."  In this case, "law" is more akin to the laws of physics than the civil law.  The necessities found in the Natural Law cannot be escaped precisely because they are necessary.  One example of a moral necessity, and part of said law, is that all men must will only what they desire.  This is about as practical as saying "all men must throw with their hands" but is nevertheless important in understanding the rules of morality, just as the necessity of throwing with one's hands is important in drafting the rules of baseball.  Nobody can choose to do something he does not desire to do (if only at least for the sake of something else) because if he chooses to do something he does not desire, he is not choosing it at all, but is rather compelled by some outside force.  (Here, perhaps, one can see what St. Thomas Aquinas meant when he posited that, if God were to “force” his will on a man, the man would still freely choose it because God would be working through the man’s will. God does not impose on a man as a master commanding a slave; rather, He works through men as the architect of his nature:  It is a poor architect who struggles against his own design. [S.T., P1, Q83, A1])

     At this point, it is now possible to show how the so-called moral imperatives are linked to moral necessities.  God, Who commanded certain acts and forbade others, establishes the Natural Law in the act of creating (and creation is not final but is ever dependent on its Creator), so His commandments are inherently linked to man’s nature, man’s ultimate purpose or end, and man’s happiness both now and in eternity.  Consider that it is a moral necessity to desire life and happiness.  Revisiting the 7th commandment once more, we are told “thou shalt not steal” because man necessarily needs material goods in order to live, it is necessary for him to live in society with other men in order to be happy, and it is impossible for a man to maintain a healthy society without mutually respect for the material goods they need.  Of course it is not impossible for a man to steal, but it is impossible to be both a thief and a good neighbor.  So, though the imperative can be ignored, the necessity cannot, and by defying the former, the latter becomes unbearable.

     The fact that man must desire what is good (because it is impossible not to) while at the same time choose to do evil is mere evidence of the fact that he is broken.  Even if he knew all the consequences of his actions, both external and innate, he would still not necessarily have the integrity to choose what he knows is good.  Men are not completely free to choose what they want or know to be good. But this does not negate the fact that each man would choose the good if it were in his power to do so.  The more one looks at the human condition of sin, his self-struggle, his incapacity to act in accord with his very nature, the more one might doubt whether there is moral necessity at all, for who can claim to act always with the clear aim of true and integral happiness, let alone claim that he has attained it?  Many people would not even admit to having even a desire for happiness.  But moral necessity, particularly that man must desire and choose the good, is rooted in a metaphysical necessity; namely, that all things are intrinsically good.  This deeper truth involves a commitment bordering on faith, the affirmation of existence, echoing the very words of its Creator, Who is nothing less than Goodness itself, “And God saw all the things that he had made, and they were very good.” (Gen 1:31)